Extended cognition: Difference between revisions
imported>John R. Brews (McGann) |
Pat Palmer (talk | contribs) (PropDel; vague and unconvincing philosophical essay) |
||
(15 intermediate revisions by 2 users not shown) | |||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
{{PropDel}}<br><br> | |||
{{subpages}} | {{subpages}} | ||
{{TOC |right}} | {{TOC |right}} | ||
'''Extended cognition''' | '''Extended cognition''' is the view that mental processes and mind extend beyond the body to include aspects of the environment in which an organism is embedded and the organism's interaction with that environment.<ref name=Rupert/> Cognition goes beyond the manipulation of symbols to include the emergence of order and structure evolving from active engagement with the world.<ref name=VanGelder/> As described by Rowlands, mental processes are:<ref name=Rowlands/> | ||
:''Embodied'' involving more than the brain, including a more general involvement of bodily structures and processes. | :''Embodied'' involving more than the brain, including a more general involvement of bodily structures and processes. | ||
:''Embedded'' functioning only in a related external environment. | :''Embedded'' functioning only in a related external environment. | ||
Line 17: | Line 18: | ||
# Descriptions and explanations of the world themselves constitute forms of social action. As such they are intertwined with the full range of other human activities. | # Descriptions and explanations of the world themselves constitute forms of social action. As such they are intertwined with the full range of other human activities. | ||
An example is the idea of a ''paradigm'' as described by [[Thomas Kuhn]] in his book [[The Structure of Scientific Revolutions]].<ref name=Guzzini/><ref name=Latour/> For the scientist a ''paradigm'' refers to the sense of the way reality is structured and the means by which the scientist uncovers this reality and is able to manipulate it and predict effects and events. The dissatisfaction of scientists with an existing theory leads to a [[paradigm shift]], and this dissatisfaction is a matter of criteria demanded of an acceptable theory.<ref name=Guzzini/> These criteria are not themselves scientifically established, but describe an 'ideal' theory as seen by the scientific community, criteria such as 'elegance', 'completeness', 'seminality', 'simplicity'.<ref name=Kuhn/><ref name=Colyvan/> | An example is the idea of a ''paradigm'' as described by [[Thomas Kuhn]] in his book [[The Structure of Scientific Revolutions]].<ref name=Guzzini/><ref name=Latour/> For the scientist a ''paradigm'' refers to the sense of the way reality is structured and the means by which the scientist uncovers this reality and is able to manipulate it and predict effects and events. The dissatisfaction of scientists with an existing theory leads to a [[paradigm shift]], and this dissatisfaction is a matter of criteria demanded of an acceptable theory.<ref name=Guzzini/> These criteria are not themselves scientifically established, but describe an 'ideal' theory as seen by the scientific community,<ref name=Bird/> criteria such as 'elegance', 'completeness', 'seminality', 'simplicity'.<ref name=Kuhn/><ref name=Colyvan/> | ||
Thus, as the idea of extended cognition suggests within the context of social constructivism, the development of a paradigm involves the interaction of scientists with their environment and each other, the theoretical treatment of experimental results, and re-engagement in probing the environment on the basis of that theory, sometimes with very sophisticated apparatus, | Thus, as the idea of extended cognition suggests within the context of social constructivism, the development of a paradigm involves the interaction of scientists with their environment and each other, the theoretical treatment of experimental results, and re-engagement in probing the environment on the basis of that theory, sometimes with very sophisticated apparatus. Examples of complex probing of the environment as part of the cognitive process, what enaction is about, are the [[Hadron collider]] or the [[Hubble telescope]]. These activities are accompanied by the evolution and application of theories subject to an aesthetic stemming from social interactions between scientists.<ref name=Kuhn/> | ||
==Non-reductive naturalism== | ==Non-reductive naturalism== | ||
[[Physical reductionism]] is the argument that all events (ultimately) are connected to (possibly yet-to-be-established) primal events by the 'laws of nature' | [[Physical reductionism]] is the argument that all events (ultimately) are connected to (possibly yet-to-be-established) primal events by the 'laws of nature'. This view leads to the anticipation that mental events are reducible to neuroscience and brain circuitry.<ref name=Kandel/> In contrast, non-reductive naturalism claims that "mental phenomena cannot be reduced to any particular material object or local process, as for instance neural processing."<ref name=Rohde/> One form of this thesis arises in [[cultural psychology]] where mind is viewed as a cultural phenomenon.<ref name=Ratner/> | ||
In contrast with a reduction of mental activity to 'brain circuitry', the manipulation of representations of sensory input by a biological computer, the view of extended cognition is ''constructivist'', that is, it is about "the active construction of knowledge through our interaction with the environment"..."Our brains do not indiscriminately and passively crunch up any structure that can be detected in a never ending stream of sensations...Cognition is a lot about ''discarding irrelevant'' information and ''going out to get relevant information''"<ref name=Rohde/><ref name=Potter/> This approach is non-reductionist, that is, it can include reductionism, but is not restricted to it. That view is similar to that of [[model-dependent realism]], namely, that a variety of models develop and adapt to our growing awareness of our environment, leading to a patchwork ensemble of overlapping descriptions, each covering their own particular domain of experience. | |||
==Internalism and externalism== | |||
{{main|Subjective-objective dichotomy}} | |||
Proponents of enaction consider its emphasis upon interaction with the external environment to be in contrast with the view of mental processes as simply the internal operation of the brain as a computer manipulating symbols encoding representations of the world, the ''rules and representations'' approach to cognition.<ref name=Rowlands/> The issue is not just that cognition involves structures outside the brain proper, but that cognition is a ''process'' of interaction, an activity. However, the role of the subject, the ''individuation'', of this activity might be underestimated.<ref name=Smith/><ref name=Lau/> | |||
The interactivity between the organism and the environment emphasized by extended cognition impinges on the deeper philosophical questions of the [[subjective-objective dichotomy]], that is the partition of experience between subject and object.<ref name=Smith/> At one extreme, our interior mental processes are dictated by interaction with the external world, and at the other extreme, they are creations of our conscious and subconscious brain activity. "''Externalism'' with regard to mental content says that in order to have certain types of intentional mental states (e.g. beliefs), it is necessary to be related to the environment in the right way. ''Internalism'' (or individualism) denies this, and it affirms that having those intentional mental states depends solely on our intrinsic properties."<ref name=Lau/> | |||
==Scaffolding== | |||
The term ''scaffolding'' in connection with mind refers to the dependence of more complicated functionality upon simpler functionality that serves as a 'scaffold' to build and develop the more complex activity. In developmental psychology one application of scaffolding is the idea that early life experiences significantly shape the adult’s understanding.<ref name=Williams/> More broadly, the term has been introduced to describe a "broad class of physical, cognitive and social augmentations -- augmentations which allow us to achieve some goal which would otherwise be beyond us".<ref name=Clark/> | |||
In the context of enaction, scaffolding refers to cognition-enhancing tools that extend mental processes into the environment and modulate or even enable interaction with that environment in the processes of cognition. A simple example is the use of a cane by a blind man, "stick-augmented perception".<ref name=Clark1/> | |||
From this standpoint, "what individuals inherit from their ancestors is not a mind, but the ability to develop a mind," a "matrix of resources that serve as the actual physical causes of development."<ref name=Griffiths/> The development of mind is seen as a dynamical process involving interaction with the environment. According to Thelan (as quoted by Griffiths and Stotz):<ref name=Thelan/> | |||
:"behavior and cognition, and their changes during ontogeny [development] are not represented anywhere in the system beforehand either as dedicated structures, or symbols in the brain, or as codes in the genes. Rather, thought and behavior are "softly assembled" as dynamical patterns of activity that arise as a function of the intended task at hand and an individual's "intrinsic dynamics" [by which is meant] the preferred states of the system given its current architecture and previous history of activity." | |||
==References== | ==References== | ||
{{reflist|refs= | {{reflist|refs= | ||
<ref name=Bird> | |||
{{cite web |author=Alexander Bird |title=Thomas Kuhn: §3: The concept of a paradigm |work=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2013 Edition) |editor=Edward N. Zalta, ed |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/thomas-kuhn/#3 |date=August 11, 2011 |quote=This [a paradigm] is the consensus on exemplary instances of scientific research. }} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Clark> | |||
{{cite book |title=Language and thought: Interdisciplinary themes |chapter=Chapter 8: Magic Words: How Language Augments Human Computation |author=Andy Clark |url=http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/courses/concepts/magicwords.html |year=1998 |pages=pp. 162-183 |editor=Peter Carruthers, Jill Boucher |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-0521637589 }} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Clark1> | |||
{{cite book |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=1cgwUvk3OiIC&pg=PA31 |pages=p. 31 |title=Supersizing the Mind : Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive Extension |year=2008 |author=Andy Clark |isbn=978-0199715534 |publisher=Oxford University Press}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Colyvan> | <ref name=Colyvan> | ||
{{cite book |title=The Indispensability of Mathematics |author=Mark Colyvan |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=OBs-TSFopLkC&pg=PA78 |pages=78–79 |isbn=0195166612 |year=2001 |publisher=Oxford University Press}} | {{cite book |title=The Indispensability of Mathematics |author=Mark Colyvan |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=OBs-TSFopLkC&pg=PA78 |pages=pp. 78–79 |isbn=0195166612 |year=2001 |publisher=Oxford University Press}} | ||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
<ref name=Gergen> | <ref name=Gergen> | ||
{{cite journal |title=The social constructionist movement in modern psychology |author=Kenneth J Gergen |journal=American Psychologist |volume=40 |issue=3 |date=March 1985 |pages=266 ''ff'' |url=http://www.swarthmore.edu/Documents/faculty/gergen/Social_Constructionist_Movement.pdf}} | {{cite journal |title=The social constructionist movement in modern psychology |author=Kenneth J Gergen |journal=American Psychologist |volume=40 |issue=3 |date=March 1985 |pages=pp. 266 ''ff'' |url=http://www.swarthmore.edu/Documents/faculty/gergen/Social_Constructionist_Movement.pdf}} | ||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Griffiths> | |||
{{cite journal |author=PE Griffiths and K Stotz |url=http://paul.representinggenes.org/webpdfs/Griff.Stotz.00.MindGrows.pdf |journal=Synthese |volume=122 |issue=1-2 |pages=pp. 29-51 |year=2000 |title=How the mind grows: a developmental perspective on the biology of cognition}} | |||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
<ref name=Guzzini> | <ref name=Guzzini> | ||
{{cite journal |author=Stefano Guzzini |title=A reconstruction of constructionism in international relations |journal=European Journal of International Relations |volume=6 |issue=2 |url=http://www.artsrn.ualberta.ca/courses/PoliticalScience/661B1/documents/GuzziniReconstructionofConstructivisminIR.pdf |year=2000 |quote=One of the main defenders of epistemological constructivism who is also well known in IR [international relations], Thomas Kuhn. | | {{cite journal |author=Stefano Guzzini |title=A reconstruction of constructionism in international relations |journal=European Journal of International Relations |volume=6 |issue=2 |url=http://www.artsrn.ualberta.ca/courses/PoliticalScience/661B1/documents/GuzziniReconstructionofConstructivisminIR.pdf |year=2000 |quote=One of the main defenders of epistemological constructivism who is also well known in IR [international relations], Thomas Kuhn. |pages=p. 158}} | ||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
<ref name=Kandel> | <ref name=Kandel> | ||
{{cite book |quote=...consciousness is a biological process that will eventually be explained in terms of molecular signaling pathways used by interacting populations of nerve cells... | | {{cite book |quote=...consciousness is a biological process that will eventually be explained in terms of molecular signaling pathways used by interacting populations of nerve cells... |pages= p. 9 |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=PFnRwWXzypgC&pg=PA9&lpg=PA9 |author=[[Eric R. Kandel]] |isbn=0393329372 |publisher=WW Norton |year=2007 |title=In Search of Memory: The Emergence of a New Science of Mind}} | ||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
<ref name=Kuhn> | <ref name=Kuhn> | ||
[[Thomas Kuhn]] formally stated the need for the "norms for rational theory choice". One of his discussions is reprinted in {{cite book |title=The Road since Structure: Philosophical Essays, 1970-1993, |author=Thomas S Kuhn |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=sXufWLnPp94C&pg=PA208 |pages=208 ''ff'' |chapter=Chapter 9: Rationality and Theory Choice |editor=James Conant, John Haugeland, eds |edition=2nd |publisher=University of Chicago Press |isbn=0226457990}} | [[Thomas Kuhn]] formally stated the need for the "norms for rational theory choice". One of his discussions is reprinted in {{cite book |title=The Road since Structure: Philosophical Essays, 1970-1993, |author=Thomas S Kuhn |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=sXufWLnPp94C&pg=PA208 |pages=pp. 208 ''ff'' |chapter=Chapter 9: Rationality and Theory Choice |editor=James Conant, John Haugeland, eds |edition=2nd |publisher=University of Chicago Press |isbn=0226457990}} | ||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
<ref name=Latour> | <ref name=Latour> | ||
{{cite book |title=Laboratory Life: The Construction of Scientific Facts |author=Bruno Latour, Steve Woolgar | | {{cite book |title=Laboratory Life: The Construction of Scientific Facts |author=Bruno Latour, Steve Woolgar |pages=p. 275 |quote=Kuhn had already provided...the general basis for a conception of the social character of science. |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=XTcjm0flPdYC&pg=PA275 |publisher=Princeton University Press |year=1986 |isbn=978-0691028323}} | ||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Lau> | |||
{{cite web |author=Joe Lau, Max Deutsch |title=Externalism About Mental Content |work=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition) |editor= Edward N. Zalta, ed |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/content-externalism/ |date=Jan 22, 2014}} | |||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
<ref name=McGann> | <ref name=McGann> | ||
{{cite journal |title=Enaction and psychology |author=McGann, Marek; De Jaegher, Hanne; Di Paolo, Ezequiel |journal=Review of General Psychology |volume= 17 |issue=2 |date=June, 2013 |pages=203-209 |doi= 10.1037/a0032935 }} | {{cite journal |title=Enaction and psychology |author=McGann, Marek; De Jaegher, Hanne; Di Paolo, Ezequiel |journal=Review of General Psychology |volume= 17 |issue=2 |date=June, 2013 |pages=pp. 203-209 |doi= 10.1037/a0032935 }} | ||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
<ref name=Morasso> | <ref name=Morasso> | ||
{{cite web |title=Consciousness as the emergent property of the interaction between brain, body, & environment: the crucial role of haptic perception |author=Pietro Morasso |url=http://www.consciousness.it/iwac2005/Material/Morasso.pdf |date=2005 }} Slides related to a chapter on [[haptic perception]] (recognition through touch): {{cite book |editor=Antonio Chella & Riccardo Manzotti, eds |author=Pietro Morasso |chapter=Chapter 14: The crucial role of haptic perception | {{cite web |title=Consciousness as the emergent property of the interaction between brain, body, & environment: the crucial role of haptic perception |author=Pietro Morasso |url=http://www.consciousness.it/iwac2005/Material/Morasso.pdf |date=2005 }} Slides related to a chapter on [[haptic perception]] (recognition through touch): {{cite book |editor=Antonio Chella & Riccardo Manzotti, eds |author=Pietro Morasso |chapter=Chapter 14: The crucial role of haptic perception |title= Artificial Consciousness |publisher= Academic |pages=pp. 234-255 |year=2007 |isbn=978-1845400705 |url=https://www.google.com/search?tbo=p&tbm=bks&q=isbn:1845400704&num=10}} | ||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
<ref name=Potter> | <ref name=Potter> | ||
{{cite book |title=50 Years of Artificial Intelligence: Essays Dedicated to the 50th Anniversary of Artificial Intelligence |editors= Max Lungarella, Fumiya Iida, Josh Bongard, Rolf Pfeifer, eds |chapter=What do we know about natural intelligence (NI) that can inform artificial intelligence (AI)? |author=SM Potter |pages=176 ''ff'' |isbn=3540772952 |year=2007 |publisher=Springer |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=vin0j1Z4fZUC&pg=PA176}} | {{cite book |title=50 Years of Artificial Intelligence: Essays Dedicated to the 50th Anniversary of Artificial Intelligence |editors= Max Lungarella, Fumiya Iida, Josh Bongard, Rolf Pfeifer, eds |chapter=What do we know about natural intelligence (NI) that can inform artificial intelligence (AI)? |author=SM Potter |pages=pp. 176 ''ff'' |isbn=3540772952 |year=2007 |publisher=Springer |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=vin0j1Z4fZUC&pg=PA176}} | ||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
<ref name=Ratner> | <ref name=Ratner> | ||
{{cite book |title=Macro Cultural Psychology: A Political Philosophy of Mind |quote=Culture produces the mind; brain circuitry does not. The [[mind-body problem]] of how the physical body/brain produces mental, subjective [[qualia]], is the wrong way to frame the origin of consciousness. | | {{cite book |title=Macro Cultural Psychology: A Political Philosophy of Mind |quote=Culture produces the mind; brain circuitry does not. The [[mind-body problem]] of how the physical body/brain produces mental, subjective [[qualia]], is the wrong way to frame the origin of consciousness. |pages=p. 96 |author=Carl Ratner |isbn=0199706298 |publisher=Oxford University Press |year=2011 |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=2ZBoAgAAQBAJ&pg=PA96#v=onepage&q=brain%20circuity&f=false}} | ||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
<ref name =Rohde> | <ref name =Rohde> | ||
{{cite book |title=Enaction, embodiment, evolutionary robotics: Simulation models for a post-cognitivist science of mind |author=Marieke Rohde |publisher= Atlantis Press |year=2010 |chapter=Introduction |isbn=978-9078677239 | | {{cite book |title=Enaction, embodiment, evolutionary robotics: Simulation models for a post-cognitivist science of mind |author=Marieke Rohde |publisher= Atlantis Press |year=2010 |chapter=Introduction |isbn=978-9078677239 |pages=p. 2}} Available on line [http://www.academia.edu/2082318/Enaction_Embodiment_Evolutionary_Robotics_Simulation_Models_for_a_Post-Cognitivist_Science_of_Mind here] | ||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
<ref name=Rowlands> | <ref name=Rowlands> | ||
{{cite book |author=Mark Rowlands |chapter=Chapter 3: The mind embedded |pages=51 ''ff'' |year=2010 |isbn=0262014556 |publisher=MIT Press |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=AiwjpL-0hDgC&pg=PA51 |title=The new science of the mind: From extended mind to embodied phenomenology}} | {{cite book |author=Mark Rowlands |chapter=Chapter 3: The mind embedded |pages=pp. 51 ''ff'' |year=2010 |isbn=0262014556 |publisher=MIT Press |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=AiwjpL-0hDgC&pg=PA51 |title=The new science of the mind: From extended mind to embodied phenomenology}} | ||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Rupert> | |||
{{cite journal |title=Challenges to the Hypothesis of Extended Cognition |author=Robert D Rupert |url=http://spot.colorado.edu/~rupertr/ExtdRev5.pdf |journal=The Journal of Philosophy |volume=101 |issue=8 |date=August 2004 |pages=pp. 389-428}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Smith> | |||
{{cite web |author=Basil Smith |title=Internalism and externalism in the philosophy of mind and language |url=http://www.iep.utm.edu/int-ex-ml/#H4 |work=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy}} | |||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
<ref name=Stewart> | <ref name=Stewart> | ||
{{cite book |title=Enaction |author=John Stewart, Oliver Gapenne, Ezequiel A DiPaolo |chapter=Introduction |editor=John Stewart, Oliver Gapenne, Ezequiel A DiPaolo, eds |publisher=MIT Press |year=2014 |isbn=978-0-262-52601-2 |edition=Paperback |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=UtFDJx-gysQC&pg=PR7}} | {{cite book |title=Enaction |author=John Stewart, Oliver Gapenne, Ezequiel A DiPaolo |chapter=Introduction |editor=John Stewart, Oliver Gapenne, Ezequiel A DiPaolo, eds |publisher=MIT Press |year=2014 |isbn=978-0-262-52601-2 |edition=Paperback |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=UtFDJx-gysQC&pg=PR7 |pages=p. ''vii''}} | ||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Thelan> | |||
{{cite book |author=Esther Thelen |chapter=Chapter 3: Time-scale dynamics and the development of an embodied cognition |title=Mind as motion: Explorations in the dynamics of cognition |year=1995) |pages=pp. 69-100 |editor=Robert F Port, Timothy van Gelder, eds |isbn=0-262-16150-8 |publisher=MIT Press |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=e6HUM6V8QbQC&pg=PA69}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=VanGelder> | |||
{{cite book |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=4dWTTVbcC-QC&pg=PA252 |author=Tim van Gelder |pages=p. 252 |chapter=Chapter 8: Wooden Iron? Husserlian Phenomenology Meets Cognitive Science |title=Naturalizing Phenomenology: Issues in Contemporary Phenomenology and Cognitive Science |isbn=978-0804736107 |editor=Jean Petitot, Francisco J Varela, Bernard Pachoud, Jean-Michel Roy, eds |year=1999 |publisher=Stanford University Press}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name=Williams> | |||
{{cite journal |title=The scaffolded mind: Higher mental processes are grounded in early experience of the physical world |author=Lawrence E Williams, Julie Y Huang, John A Baruch |url=http://www.yale.edu/acmelab/articles/Scaffolded_Mind_EJSP.pdf |journal=European Journal of Social Psychology |volume=39 |issue=7 |year=2009 |pages=pp. 1257-1267}} | |||
</ref> | </ref> | ||
}} | }}[[Category:Suggestion Bot Tag]] |
Latest revision as of 09:18, 21 October 2024
This article may be deleted soon. | ||
---|---|---|
Extended cognition is the view that mental processes and mind extend beyond the body to include aspects of the environment in which an organism is embedded and the organism's interaction with that environment.[1] Cognition goes beyond the manipulation of symbols to include the emergence of order and structure evolving from active engagement with the world.[2] As described by Rowlands, mental processes are:[3]
It has been customary to think of the mind as a processing center that creates mental representations of reality and uses them to control the body's behavior. The field of extended cognition focuses upon the processes involved in this creation, and subsumes these processes as part of 'mind'. As a result, mind is no longer confined to the brain or body, but involves interaction with the environment. At a 'low' level, like motor learning, haptic perception,[4] and psycholinguistics the body is obviously involved in cognition, but it is equally obvious that there is a 'high' level where cultural factors play a role.[5][6] This broadened view of cognition and cognitive science is sometimes referred to as enaction to emphasize the role of interplay between the organism and its environment and the feedback processes involved in developing an awareness of, and a reformation of, the environment.[7] The emphasis on the interactive nature of cognition includes but extends the idea of embodied cognition, which last recognizes the extension of 'mind' beyond the confines of the brain, but does not emphasize the interactive learning process. Social constructivismExtended cognition involves groups as well as individuals. Social constructivism is the study of an individual's learning that takes place because of their interactions in a group, and the group's experience with its environment. According to Gergen, the social constructionist orientation suggests:[8]
An example is the idea of a paradigm as described by Thomas Kuhn in his book The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.[9][10] For the scientist a paradigm refers to the sense of the way reality is structured and the means by which the scientist uncovers this reality and is able to manipulate it and predict effects and events. The dissatisfaction of scientists with an existing theory leads to a paradigm shift, and this dissatisfaction is a matter of criteria demanded of an acceptable theory.[9] These criteria are not themselves scientifically established, but describe an 'ideal' theory as seen by the scientific community,[11] criteria such as 'elegance', 'completeness', 'seminality', 'simplicity'.[12][13] Thus, as the idea of extended cognition suggests within the context of social constructivism, the development of a paradigm involves the interaction of scientists with their environment and each other, the theoretical treatment of experimental results, and re-engagement in probing the environment on the basis of that theory, sometimes with very sophisticated apparatus. Examples of complex probing of the environment as part of the cognitive process, what enaction is about, are the Hadron collider or the Hubble telescope. These activities are accompanied by the evolution and application of theories subject to an aesthetic stemming from social interactions between scientists.[12] Non-reductive naturalismPhysical reductionism is the argument that all events (ultimately) are connected to (possibly yet-to-be-established) primal events by the 'laws of nature'. This view leads to the anticipation that mental events are reducible to neuroscience and brain circuitry.[14] In contrast, non-reductive naturalism claims that "mental phenomena cannot be reduced to any particular material object or local process, as for instance neural processing."[15] One form of this thesis arises in cultural psychology where mind is viewed as a cultural phenomenon.[5] In contrast with a reduction of mental activity to 'brain circuitry', the manipulation of representations of sensory input by a biological computer, the view of extended cognition is constructivist, that is, it is about "the active construction of knowledge through our interaction with the environment"..."Our brains do not indiscriminately and passively crunch up any structure that can be detected in a never ending stream of sensations...Cognition is a lot about discarding irrelevant information and going out to get relevant information"[15][16] This approach is non-reductionist, that is, it can include reductionism, but is not restricted to it. That view is similar to that of model-dependent realism, namely, that a variety of models develop and adapt to our growing awareness of our environment, leading to a patchwork ensemble of overlapping descriptions, each covering their own particular domain of experience. Internalism and externalismProponents of enaction consider its emphasis upon interaction with the external environment to be in contrast with the view of mental processes as simply the internal operation of the brain as a computer manipulating symbols encoding representations of the world, the rules and representations approach to cognition.[3] The issue is not just that cognition involves structures outside the brain proper, but that cognition is a process of interaction, an activity. However, the role of the subject, the individuation, of this activity might be underestimated.[17][18] The interactivity between the organism and the environment emphasized by extended cognition impinges on the deeper philosophical questions of the subjective-objective dichotomy, that is the partition of experience between subject and object.[17] At one extreme, our interior mental processes are dictated by interaction with the external world, and at the other extreme, they are creations of our conscious and subconscious brain activity. "Externalism with regard to mental content says that in order to have certain types of intentional mental states (e.g. beliefs), it is necessary to be related to the environment in the right way. Internalism (or individualism) denies this, and it affirms that having those intentional mental states depends solely on our intrinsic properties."[18] ScaffoldingThe term scaffolding in connection with mind refers to the dependence of more complicated functionality upon simpler functionality that serves as a 'scaffold' to build and develop the more complex activity. In developmental psychology one application of scaffolding is the idea that early life experiences significantly shape the adult’s understanding.[19] More broadly, the term has been introduced to describe a "broad class of physical, cognitive and social augmentations -- augmentations which allow us to achieve some goal which would otherwise be beyond us".[20] In the context of enaction, scaffolding refers to cognition-enhancing tools that extend mental processes into the environment and modulate or even enable interaction with that environment in the processes of cognition. A simple example is the use of a cane by a blind man, "stick-augmented perception".[21] From this standpoint, "what individuals inherit from their ancestors is not a mind, but the ability to develop a mind," a "matrix of resources that serve as the actual physical causes of development."[22] The development of mind is seen as a dynamical process involving interaction with the environment. According to Thelan (as quoted by Griffiths and Stotz):[23]
References
|